/* tertium quid - Part 1 Section 1 */

tertium quid

exploring fundamental mind and a post-physicalist narrative


Part 1 Section 1

The Story We’ve Inherited

From Living Cosmos to Clockwork Universe

The Premodern World: Cosmos as Living Whole

To the premodern mind, both in the philosophical schools of ancient Greece and in the animistic worldview of many Indigenous cultures, the cosmos was not an inert backdrop for human action but was itself a living, intelligent, and relational whole. This was a world defined by participation, not detached observation. Spirit, in some form, permeated the cosmos; a river or a mountain was not merely an object to be analyzed but an agent or a presence to be related to, possessing its own interiority and purpose. The foundational experience was one of belonging to an animate reality, a stark contrast to the modern view of humanity as a lonely, conscious spectator in a dead, mechanical universe.

This ancient intuition of a living cosmos was not simply a matter of folk belief; it was formalized and given profound intellectual structure by the earliest and most influential philosophers in the West. Early Western philosophy, far from being materialist, posited a universe imbued with mind and purpose. For Plato, the physical world was a moving image of an eternal, intelligible reality, and the cosmos itself was a single, living creature endowed with a World Soul and a cosmic intellect (nous) that brought order and reason to the material realm. His student, Aristotle, while more grounded in empirical observation, likewise saw the world as saturated with purpose. He argued that all natural things possess a telos, an innate, indwelling end toward which they strive—the telos of an acorn is to become a mighty oak, and this striving is an intrinsic part of its nature.

For these foundational thinkers, qualities that are now considered merely subjective—warmth, purpose, color, even soul—were irreducible and real features of the world. Reality was not divided into “primary” and “secondary” qualities, but was understood as a seamless whole in which mathematical relationships coexisted with meaning, beauty, and intention. The cosmos was intelligible precisely because it was intelligent; it could be known because it was, in some fundamental sense, akin to mind itself.

The Medieval Synthesis: Cosmos, Creation, and Meaning

This integrated vision of a meaningful cosmos was not discarded with the rise of Christianity, but was instead absorbed and transformed by the next great intellectual movement in the West. The medieval period synthesized this classical philosophical heritage with Christian theology to produce a powerful and remarkably coherent vision of an ordered, meaningful, and God-infused cosmos. The core logic of the medieval synthesis held that the universe was fundamentally intelligible because it was the creation of a rational, divine mind. Nature was seen as a “second book,” a divine text that, like Scripture, revealed the mind of its author.

This worldview found its most famous expression in the concept of the Great Chain of Being, a model that organized all of existence—from God and the angelic hosts down to the most humble stone—in a single, unbroken, and value-laden hierarchy. Everything had its proper place and its purpose within this divine order. Within such a framework, the practice of what we would now call science was not seen as an alternative or a threat to theology, but as a form of it. To study the natural world was to engage in a fundamentally spiritual act: to read the mind of God as expressed in the rational structure of creation.

For the great minds of the early Scientific Revolution, like the astronomer Johannes Kepler and the physicist Isaac Newton, scientific inquiry was a deeply spiritual pursuit. It was an act of deciphering the rational mind of God as it was expressed in the sublime mathematical laws of nature. Kepler, upon discerning the elliptical orbits of the planets, famously exclaimed his desire was “only to taste the flavor of seeing, if I could, with my own eyes, what I had learned from the mouth of God.”1 He believed he was thinking God’s thoughts after Him. Similarly, Newton, a profoundly religious man who wrote more on theology than on physics, saw his discovery of universal gravitation not as evidence of a self-sufficient mechanism, but as proof of God’s ongoing, rational design and dominion over the cosmos.

For these pivotal figures, there was no conflict between physics and faith; they were integrated paths to understanding a single, divinely ordered reality. The mathematical elegance they discovered in planetary motion and terrestrial mechanics was not mere utility—it was a glimpse into the aesthetic and rational perfection of divine creativity. Yet, the very power and elegance of the system Newton created contained the seeds of a profound transformation that would ultimately remove its creator from the picture.

The Scientific Revolution: The Great Divorce

Between the 16th and 18th centuries, a profound conceptual shift occurred: the primary language for describing reality moved from quality and purpose to quantity and mechanism. This transformation did not happen overnight, nor was it the conscious intention of its architects. Rather, it emerged through a series of methodological choices that proved so successful that they gradually hardened into metaphysical commitments.

Galileo Galilei was a key architect of this change, redefining science as the study of what is measurable and declaring mathematics to be its proper language. His famous declaration that “the book of nature is written in mathematical characters” represented more than a methodological preference—it implied that what could not be mathematized was somehow less real, less worthy of serious attention. Shortly thereafter, René Descartes provided the philosophical architecture for this new science with his ontological dualism. By splitting reality into two distinct and incompatible substances—inert, extended, mechanical matter (res extensa) and un-extended, private, thinking mind (res cogitans)—Descartes effectively exiled mind and all its qualities from the physical world.

This conceptual divorce of mind from matter set the stage for a gradual but profound reinterpretation of Newton’s work. Here we encounter one of the most consequential intellectual drifts in Western history: a slow but decisive shift that would reshape human consciousness over the course of generations.

The Great Conceptual Drift

Over the course of more than a century, a profound conceptual drift took place in European thought: the mathematical tools that were so successful at modeling the behavior of the world gradually came to be seen as a complete description of the world itself. This transformation represents what we might call the confusion of the map with the territory—but it was a confusion that developed slowly, almost imperceptibly, across multiple generations.

The drift began with the undeniable predictive power of mathematical modeling. Newton’s equations could predict eclipses, calculate trajectories, and explain the tides with unprecedented precision. This was genuinely revolutionary—for the first time in human history, natural phenomena could be predicted with mathematical exactitude. The success was so spectacular that it seemed to validate not just the method, but the entire worldview that accompanied it.

What happened next was more subtle: what began as a methodological limitation—the decision to study only what could be measured—gradually became an ontological claim about what was real. Qualities like color, beauty, meaning, and purpose, which could not be captured by the new mechanical equations, were deemed “secondary qualities”—not real features of the world, but subjective projections of the isolated human mind. The elegant, predictive power of Newton’s mechanics allowed subsequent thinkers, most famously the French mathematician Pierre-Simon Laplace, to envision a “clockwork universe.”

When asked by Napoleon where God fit into his cosmic system, Laplace is said to have replied, “I had no need of that hypothesis.”2 He had articulated the vision of a perfect, deterministic machine that, once set in motion, required no ongoing divine agency or purpose. This marks the moment of what Alfred North Whitehead would later call the “bifurcation of nature,” where the seamless, meaningful whole of the premodern world was decisively cleaved in two.

What makes this transformation so historically significant is not merely that it changed how we understood the world, but that it changed what we considered worth understanding. The mathematical model, originally designed as a tool for prediction and control, gradually became the standard for what counted as real knowledge. Anything that could not be quantified, measured, or reduced to mechanical terms was slowly relegated to the realm of the subjective, the private, the ultimately illusory.

This drift was so gradual that each generation of thinkers could reasonably see themselves as simply building on their predecessors’ work, not fundamentally altering humanity’s relationship to reality. Yet by the end of the process, the seamless, meaningful cosmos of the ancients had been replaced by something entirely different: a collection of mindless particles moving according to mathematical laws, with consciousness relegated to the status of an emergent accident.

The Enlightenment and Human Exceptionalism

This newly disenchanted, mechanical cosmos set the stage for the final step in the evolution of the modern worldview: the construction of meaning by humanity alone. Enlightenment thinkers extended this mechanistic thinking from the cosmos to society, politics, and ethics, proposing that meaning was no longer to be discovered in a divinely ordered world but was to be constructed by human reason alone.

God, for many of the period’s intellectuals, became unnecessary—not disproved, but functionally replaced by the power of the human intellect. This was not necessarily atheism in the militant sense, but rather a practical agnosticism: whether or not God existed became irrelevant to the business of understanding and organizing the world. Human reason, armed with the scientific method, could do the work that had once required divine revelation.

The concept of “progress” emerged as a central cultural myth: humanity would perfect itself and the world through knowledge and control, not through alignment with a cosmic or divine order. This represented a fundamental reorientation of human purpose. Where traditional cultures had seen the goal of life as harmony with a meaningful cosmos, the Enlightenment redefined it as the rational transformation of the world according to human designs.

This powerful shift paved the way for a new, secular form of transcendence. Technology gradually became the new locus of salvation, with the scientific and engineering enterprise inheriting the redemptive arc that had once belonged to religion. As the historian David Noble has persuasively argued, the modern technological project is, in many ways, a secularized religious mission, driven by “a religious striving for transcendence and salvation.”3

Human salvation was subtly redefined from alignment with spirit to mastery over nature. The future was not something to be received with grace or humility, but something to be engineered and controlled through human ingenuity. This shift is so fundamental to the modern worldview that we rarely recognize its radical novelty: the idea that humans are separate from nature and destined to control it would have been nearly incomprehensible to most of our ancestors.

The Consequences: Disenchantment and Disconnection

The final result of this long historical process was a universe radically different from the one our ancestors inhabited. The price of this newfound predictive power was a profound existential dislocation, leaving humanity in an inert, mindless, and indifferent cosmos. In the story we inherited from this period, consciousness is cast as an emergent illusion, a ghost in the machine—real only in the sense that a rainbow is “real,” a surface effect of underlying physical processes that are themselves devoid of interiority or purpose.

Value and meaning become purely subjective whims, bracketed off from a “real” world of objective facts. This creates a peculiar dualism: everything we actually care about—beauty, purpose, love, moral obligation, spiritual longing—is rendered epistemologically suspect, while the only “real” world is the one devoid of care, purpose, or meaning. Nature, stripped of its interiority and agency, becomes a mere resource to be managed and exploited. The human mind itself is reduced to software running on the biological hardware of the brain.

Perhaps most significantly, this worldview generates what we might call “the paradox of human exceptionalism.” On one hand, humans are the only conscious beings in a mindless universe, the sole carriers of meaning in a meaningless cosmos. On the other hand, human consciousness itself is explained as nothing but the mechanical operation of neurons—meaningful only as an illusion, real only as a byproduct. We are simultaneously elevated above nature (as its only conscious observers) and reduced within it (as complex machines).

The psychological toll of this paradox is profound, though often unrecognized. Modern people find themselves in the peculiar position of being told that everything they most deeply experience—love, beauty, moral obligation, spiritual longing, the very sense of being a self—is somehow less real than the colorless, purposeless particles supposedly underlying these experiences. We are asked to believe that our most intimate experiences are the least reliable guides to reality, while mathematical equations and neurological correlates reveal the ultimate truth about our condition.

This creates a kind of existential vertigo. If consciousness is an illusion, who is experiencing the illusion? If meaning is just a trick of evolution, why does the absence of meaning feel so devastating? If we are nothing but complex machines, why do we suffer so acutely from being treated as such? The mechanistic worldview asks us to stand outside our own experience and judge it unreal—a psychological contortion that may be literally impossible to sustain.

The symptoms of this impossible position manifest throughout contemporary culture: the epidemic of depression and anxiety in materially prosperous societies, the desperate search for meaning through consumption or achievement, the oscillation between cold rationalism and reactive spiritualism, the pervasive sense of alienation from nature and from each other. These are not merely personal failings but the predictable consequences of trying to live within a worldview that systematically invalidates the very experiences that make life worth living.

The Persistence of the Old Story

Despite this immense psychological cost, this mechanistic story persists for powerful reasons. The mechanistic worldview continues its reign today not because it is philosophically complete or spiritually satisfying, but because of its undeniable technological efficacy, its deep institutional entrenchment in our educational and economic systems, and the lack of a coherent, widely-known alternative.

The technological argument is the most obvious: this worldview works. It has given us antibiotics and space travel, computers and genetic engineering. When a perspective delivers such tangible benefits, questioning its foundational assumptions can seem like dangerous ingratitude, even irrationality. The institutional argument is equally powerful: mechanistic materialism is now so deeply embedded in our universities, research institutions, and funding agencies that alternative approaches struggle to gain a hearing, let alone resources.

But perhaps most importantly, its core assumptions have become so pervasive as to be invisible, mistaken for objective truth rather than what they are: one possible map of the territory. We no longer recognize that we are operating within a particular worldview; instead, we mistake this worldview for reality itself. The mechanistic perspective has achieved what all successful ideologies achieve: it has made itself seem like common sense.

A Fork in the Road

The current moment, however, defined by converging ecological, psychological, and spiritual crises born from this very worldview, presents us with a fork in the road. The same perspective that gave us unprecedented power over the natural world has also given us climate change, mass extinction, and a spiritual crisis that manifests as depression, anxiety, and a pervasive sense of meaninglessness among those who should, by material standards, be the most fortunate humans in history.

We are invited to imagine something more, to seek a story that can reintegrate what was so decisively torn apart. This does not mean abandoning the genuine insights of science, but rather recognizing that the reductionist interpretation of those insights may be neither necessary nor accurate. As we will explore, the very foundations of this mechanistic worldview—from quantum mechanics to the nature of consciousness—are far shakier than is commonly assumed.

The question before us is not whether we should return to a pre-scientific worldview—that path is neither possible nor desirable. The question is whether we can move forward to a post-reductionist understanding that honors both the power of scientific method and the reality of meaning, consciousness, and interiority. The stakes could hardly be higher: not just our intellectual coherence, but our capacity to live as full human beings in a world worth caring about.

As we will see, this recovery of a more complete vision of reality finds unexpected support from the cutting edges of science itself, from the strange world of quantum mechanics to the remarkable intelligence of non-human life. The mechanistic worldview, presented for centuries as the final word on the nature of reality, may instead prove to be a crucial but ultimately provisional chapter in humanity’s ongoing effort to understand its place in the cosmos.



  1. Johannes Kepler, in a letter to Herwart von Hohenburg, 1599. ↩︎

  2. This quote is famously attributed to Laplace, though its exact wording is a matter of historical debate. It captures the essence of his deterministic worldview. ↩︎

  3. David F. Noble, The Religion of Technology: The Divinity of Man and the Spirit of Invention (New York: Penguin Books, 1999), 4. ↩︎