/* tertium quid - Part 1 Section 2 */

tertium quid

exploring fundamental mind and a post-physicalist narrative


Part 1 Section 2

The Birth of Scientism

The immense cultural authority of modern science stems directly from the undeniable power of its core method. At its heart, science is a disciplined practice of observation, hypothesis formation, rigorous testing, and a radical commitment to falsifiability—the principle that any valid scientific claim must, in principle, be disprovable. Its proper domain is the creation of predictive models that describe the measurable relationships between physical phenomena, and its success in this domain is unparalleled, forming the foundation of our entire technological civilization. We owe to scientific method our antibiotics and anesthetics, our understanding of genetics and global climate patterns, our ability to split atoms and land rovers on Mars. These achievements represent one of humanity’s greatest intellectual triumphs, and any credible worldview must fully acknowledge them.

However, the very success of this powerful method has led to a quiet but consequential philosophical error: a conflation of the method with a totalizing worldview. Over time, the methodological principle of focusing only on what is measurable has subtly hardened into an ontological assumption that only the measurable is real. This is a subtle but profound slide. What science can successfully quantify—mass, charge, velocity, location—becomes implicitly equated with what truly exists. Conversely, that which the scientific method cannot, at least currently, measure or model—consciousness, value, purpose, beauty—is quietly dismissed as secondary, illusory, or simply not real. This elevation of a method into a metaphysics has a name: scientism.

It is crucial to distinguish science, the method, from scientism, the ideology. Scientism is not science; it is the philosophical belief that the scientific method is the only valid path to genuine knowledge. This belief is not itself a scientific finding but a metaphysical or ideological position. As the philosopher of science E.A. Burtt noted, no experiment can ever prove that science is the only way to acquire knowledge.1 The core tenets of scientism, often held implicitly, include an ontological reductionism which claims that reality consists only of physical objects and forces; an epistemological chauvinism which holds that any claim that cannot be mathematically modeled or instrumentally verified is not genuine knowledge; and an explanatory imperialism which insists that all phenomena, including the deepest aspects of human life, must ultimately be “explained away” as artifacts of biology or physics.

This ideological stance was not the original intent of the pioneers of modern science, nor was it necessary for their discoveries. The transition from a powerful scientific method to a restrictive scientistic metaphysics was a gradual and largely unconscious process, driven by intellectual momentum and the sheer weight of success. As we saw in the previous section, early modern thinkers like Newton and Kepler were not reductionists. They sought to understand the laws of God or the deep rationality of nature, not to exclude mind or meaning from the cosmos. Even Charles Darwin saw himself as a naturalist describing a process, not a philosopher intending to reduce all of life to mere purposeless mechanism. Einstein, despite his famous skepticism about quantum indeterminacy, maintained a profound sense of cosmic mystery and explicitly rejected the notion that science could answer all meaningful questions about existence.

Over time, however, the explanatory power of mechanical models began to masquerade as ontological sufficiency. Because the models worked so well in their proper domain—predicting planetary motions, designing machines, curing diseases—the assumptions built into them were mistaken for discoveries about the nature of reality itself. In the most fundamental philosophical error imaginable, the map became the territory. The breathtaking success of scientific method in understanding and manipulating the physical world led to the unfounded assumption that physical description exhausts reality.

The Expulsion of the Qualitative

The philosophical groundwork for this expulsion of the qualitative was laid by John Locke’s famous distinction between “primary” and “secondary” qualities. Primary qualities, like shape, size, and motion, were thought to exist in objects themselves, independent of any observer. Secondary qualities, like color, sound, taste, and warmth, were said to exist only in the mind of the perceiver, generated by the interaction between the primary qualities of the object and the sense organs. This move effectively created two worlds: a “real” outer world of colorless, soundless, meaningless particles in motion, and an “unreal” inner world of purely subjective experience. While this distinction served important methodological purposes—allowing science to focus on what could be precisely measured—scientism takes this useful philosophical distinction and turns it into a metaphysical declaration of reality.

Scientism thus creates its own strange and untenable dualism, in which everything that makes life meaningful is rendered epistemologically suspect. In this view, the “real” world is the one devoid of care, purpose, or meaning. Human experience—love, grief, moral intuition, aesthetic awe—is relegated to the status of a subjective surface effect, a neurological shimmer on the surface of an unfeeling physical machine. The very ground of our existence, our own conscious awareness, is treated as a kind of phantom. This impoverished worldview is maintained and propagated through a powerful aura of institutional authority.

The New Priesthood

In the modern secular world, science and its designated experts have come to occupy the social role once held by theology and its priesthood: a final guarantor of truth. This cultural authority is bolstered by an “aura of objectivity” and the rhetorical power of phrases like “studies show,” “the science is settled,” or “according to the data.” While this language can reflect genuine scientific consensus on well-established findings, it often masks the provisional, model-dependent nature of all scientific knowledge, creating an intellectual climate that can be surprisingly resistant to challenges of its core assumptions.

The consequence of scientism’s cultural dominance is the systemic downgrading of other essential human disciplines. Philosophy, ethics, spirituality, and the arts are repositioned as “soft” or purely subjective “ways of knowing,” seen as inferior to the “hard” knowledge produced by empirical science. Within this climate, to question the underlying materialist assumptions is often framed not as a legitimate philosophical inquiry, but as an irrational, “unscientific,” or dangerously foolish act. In this way, scientism functions less like an open method of inquiry and more like a closed belief system, complete with its own set of unexamined dogmas.

It is important to note that many working scientists themselves do not subscribe to scientistic ideology. They recognize the limits of their methods and maintain intellectual humility about what science can and cannot address. The problem lies not with scientific practice, but with the cultural elevation of that practice into a totalizing worldview.

Scientism as Secular Religion

As historians like David Noble have argued, scientism provides a new, secular mythology that replaces traditional religious eschatology with a faith in technological progress. Salvation is redefined, not as union with the divine, but as liberation from natural constraints like disease, aging, and even death through technological control. The future is not something to be awaited with humility, but something to be engineered. Science, in this sense, offers its own mythic elements: a grand origin story in the Big Bang, powerful saviors in the form of AI and genetic engineering, and an expert priesthood that can interpret the sacred texts of data.

This quasi-religious stance of scientism, however, retains all the certainty of dogmatic religion but jettisons the humility, reverence, and sense of mystery that gave traditional spiritual paths their depth and wisdom. It replaces wonder with explanation, and awe with the prospect of control. It is a belief system that, by its own internal logic, cannot recognize its own limits, because it has defined its own methods as the sole arbiters of reality.

The Costs Without Benefits

What positive contributions has scientism, as distinct from science itself, actually made? This is a crucial question for intellectual honesty. While science has given us antibiotics, space exploration, and digital technology, scientism as an ideology appears to have contributed little beyond the problems it has created. The debunking of harmful superstitions came from scientific evidence and rational inquiry, not from the philosophical claim that science is the only valid knowledge. The promotion of intellectual rigor emerged from scientific method, not from scientistic metaphysics.

Instead, scientism seems to have produced mainly costs: the dismissal of meaning and value as “unreal,” the reduction of human experience to neural chemistry, the treatment of nature as mere resource rather than relation. Perhaps most ironically, scientism may actually hinder scientific progress by constraining imagination and closing off avenues of inquiry that don’t fit its narrow metaphysical assumptions.

The Cracks Begin to Show

Despite its triumphs, the scientistic worldview is now facing deep and persistent challenges from both within science and from the undeniable data of human experience. The Hard Problem of consciousness remains completely unsolved, a “ghost in the machine” that refuses to be exorcised. The persistent failure of the materialist framework to explain value, meaning, or interiority leaves a vast domain of human reality untouched. And, as we will explore, discoveries in fundamental physics, biology, and systems science actively resist simple, bottom-up reductionist interpretation.

Even within the scientific community, there is growing recognition that materialism may be an incomplete foundation for understanding reality. The interpretation of quantum mechanics remains hotly debated precisely because the mathematical formalism seems to resist any simple materialist reading. The emergence of complex systems displays properties that cannot be predicted from knowledge of their parts alone. The study of consciousness in neuroscience has revealed the inadequacy of computational metaphors for understanding subjective experience.

There is a growing sense among a diverse range of thinkers that the map we’ve inherited is powerful but fundamentally incomplete. We may be standing on the threshold of another kind of knowing, one that requires a new kind of science and a more expansive philosophy to fully embrace. This need not mean abandoning scientific rigor, but rather expanding our conception of what counts as rigorous inquiry to include the full spectrum of human experience and cosmic reality.



  1. E.A. Burtt, The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Science (New York: Dover Publications, 2003). A classic analysis of the unstated philosophical assumptions that underlie modern science. ↩︎